previous
index
next
Aristotle
Michael Fowler, UVa Physics
Beginnings of Science and Philosophy in Athens
Let us first recap briefly the emergence of philosophy and science in Athens after around 450 B.C. It all began with Socrates, who was born in 470 B.C.
Socrates was a true philosopher, a lover of wisdom, who tried to elicit the
truth by what has become known as the Socratic method, in which by a series of
probing questions he forced successive further clarification of thought. Of course,
such clarity often reveals that the other person’s ideas don’t in
fact make much sense, so that although Socrates made a lot of things much
clearer, he wasn’t a favorite of many establishment politicians. For
example, he could argue very convincingly that traditional morality had no
logical basis. He mostly lectured to the sons of well-to-do aristocrats, one of
whom was Plato, born in 428 B.C. Plato was a young man when Athens
was humiliated by Sparta in the Peloponnesian War, and Plato probably attributed
the loss to Athens’ being a democracy, as opposed to the kind of fascist
war-based state Sparta was. Plato founded an Academy. The name came (at least
in legend) from one Academus, a landowner on whose estate Plato and
other philosophers met regularly. The important point is that this was the
first university. All the people involved were probably aristocrats, and they
discussed everything: politics, economics, morality, philosophy, mathematics
and science. One of their main concerns was to find what constituted an ideal
city-state. Democracy didn’t seem to have worked very well in their
recent past. Plato’s ideas are set out in the Republic.
Plato’s Idea of a Good Education
What is interesting about the Republic from our point of view is the
emphasis on a good education for the elite group in charge of Plato’s
ideal society. In particular, Plato considered education in mathematics and
astronomy to be excellent ways of sharpening the mind. He believed that intense
mental exercise of this kind had the same effect on the mind that a rigorous
physical regimen did on the body. Students at the Academy covered a vast range
of subjects, but there was a sign over the door stating that some knowledge of mathematics
was needed to enter—nothing else was mentioned! Plato in particular loved
geometry, and felt that the beauty of the five regular solids he was the first
to categorize meant they must be fundamental to nature, they must somehow be
the shapes of the atoms. Notice that this approach to physics is not heavily
dependent on observation and experiment.
Aristotle and Alexander
We turn now to the third member of this trio, Aristotle, born in 384
B.C. in Stagira, in Thrace, at the northern end of the Aegean, near Macedonia.
Aristotle’s father was the family physician of King Philip of Macedonia.
At the age of eighteen, Aristotle came to Athens to study at Plato’s
Academy, and stayed there twenty years until Plato’s death in 348 B.C. (Statue
is a Roman copy of a Greek original, in the Louvre, photographer Eric Gaba (User:Sting),
July 2005.)
Five years after Plato’s death, Aristotle took a position as tutor to
King Philip of Macedonia’s thirteen year old son Alexander. He stayed for
three years. It is not clear what impact, if any, Aristotle’s lessons
had, but Alexander, like his father, was a great admirer of Greek civilization,
even though the Athenians considered Macedonia the boondocks. In fact, when his
father Philip died in 336 B.C., Alexander did his best to spread Greek
civilization as far as he could. Macedonia had an excellent army, and over the
next thirteen years Alexander organized Greece as a federation of city states,
conquered Persia, the Middle East, Egypt, southern Afghanistan, some of Central
Asia and the Punjab in India.
The picture below is a fortress built by Alexander’s army in Herat,
Afghanistan, and still standing. (Picture from //flickr.com/photos/koldo/67606119/
, author koldo / Koldo Hormaza .)
He founded Greek cities in many places, the greatest being Alexandria in
Egypt, which in fact became the most important center of Greek science later
on, and without which all of Greek learning might have been lost. The Greek
cities became restless, predictably but rather ungratefully, when he
demanded to be treated as a god. He died of a fever at age 33.
Aristotle Founds the Lyceum
Aristotle came back to Athens in 335 B.C., and spent the next twelve years
running his own version of an academy, which was called the Lyceum, named after
the place in Athens where it was located, an old temple of Apollo.
(French high schools are named lycee after Aristotle’s
establishment.) Aristotle’s preferred mode of operation was to spend a
lot of time walking around talking with his colleagues, then write down his
arguments. The Aristotelians are often called the Peripatetics: people who walk
around.
Aristotle wrote extensively on all subjects: politics, metaphysics, ethics,
logic and science. He didn’t care for Plato’s rather communal
Utopia, in which the women were shared by the men, and the children raised by
everybody, because for one thing he feared the children would be raised by
nobody. His ideal society was one run by cultured gentlemen. He saw nothing
wrong with slavery, provided the slave was naturally inferior to the master, so
slaves should not be Greeks. This all sounds uncomfortably similar to
Jefferson’s Virginia, perhaps not too surprising since Greek was a
central part of a gentleman’s education in Jefferson’s day.
Aristotle’s Science
Aristotle’s approach to science differed from Plato’s. He agreed
that the highest human faculty was reason, and its supreme activity was
contemplation. However, in addition to studying what he called “first
philosophy” - metaphysics and mathematics, the things Plato had worked
on, Aristotle thought it also very important to study “second
philosophy”: the world around us, from physics and mechanics to biology.
Perhaps being raised in the house of a physician had given him an interest in
living things.
What he achieved in those years in Athens was to begin a school of organized
scientific inquiry on a scale far exceeding anything that had gone before. He
first clearly defined what was scientific knowledge, and why it should be
sought. In other words, he single-handedly invented science as the collective,
organized enterprise it is today. Plato’s Academy had the equivalent of a
university mathematics department, Aristotle had the first science department,
truly excellent in biology, but, as we shall see, a little weak in physics.
After Aristotle, there was no comparable professional science enterprise for
over 2,000 years, and his work was of such quality that it was accepted by all,
and had long been a part of the official orthodoxy of the Christian Church
2,000 years later. This was unfortunate, because when Galileo questioned some
of the assertions concerning simple physics, he quickly found himself in
serious trouble with the Church.
Aristotle’s Method
Aristotle’s method of investigation varied from one natural science to
another, depending on the problems encountered, but it usually included:
1. defining the subject matter,
2. considering the difficulties involved by reviewing the
generally accepted views on the subject, and suggestions of earlier
writers.
3. presenting his own arguments and solutions.
Again, this is the pattern modern research papers follow, Aristotle was
laying down the standard professional approach to scientific research. The
arguments he used were of two types: dialectical, that is, based on
logical deduction; and empirical, based on practical considerations.
Aristotle often refuted an opposing argument by showing that it led to an
absurd conclusion, this is called reductio ad absurdum (reducing
something to absurdity). As we shall see later, Galileo used exactly this kind
of argument against Aristotle himself, to the great annoyance of Aristotelians
2,000 years after Aristotle.
Another possibility was that an argument led to a dilemma: an
apparent contradiction. However, dilemmas could sometimes be resolved by
realizing that there was some ambiguity in a definition, say, so precision
of definitions and usage of terms is essential to productive
discussion in any discipline.
“Causes”
In contrast to Plato, who felt the only worthwhile science to be the
contemplation of abstract forms, Aristotle practiced detailed observation and
dissection of plants and animals, to try to understand how each fitted into the
grand scheme of nature, and the importance of the different organs of animals.
His motivation is made clear by the following quote from him (in Lloyd, p105):
For even in those kinds [of animals] that are not attractive to the
senses, yet to the intellect the craftsmanship of nature provides extraordinary
pleasures for those who can recognize the causes in things and who are
naturally inclined to philosophy.
His study of nature was a search for “causes.” What, exactly are
these “causes”? He gave some examples (we follow Lloyd’s
discussion here). He stated that any object (animal, plant, inanimate,
whatever) had four attributes:
matter
form
moving cause
final cause
For a table, the matter is wood, the form is the shape, the moving cause is
the carpenter and the final cause is the reason the table was made in the first
place, for a family to eat at, for example. For man, he thought the matter was
provided by the mother, the form was a rational two-legged animal, the moving
cause was the father and the final cause was to become a fully grown human
being. He did not believe nature to be conscious, he believed this final cause
to be somehow innate in a human being, and similarly in other organisms. Of
course, fulfilling this final cause is not inevitable, some accident may
intervene, but apart from such exceptional circumstances, nature is regular and
orderly.
To give another example of this central concept, he thought the “final
cause” of an acorn was to be an oak tree. This has also been translated
by Bertrand Russell (History of Western Philosophy) as the
“nature” of an acorn is to become an oak tree. It is certainly very
natural on viewing the living world, especially the maturing of complex
organisms, to view them as having innately the express purpose of developing
into their final form.
It is interesting to note that this whole approach to studying nature fits
very well with Christianity. The idea that every organism is beautifully
crafted for a particular function - its “final cause” - in the
grand scheme of nature certainly leads naturally to the thought that all this
has been designed by somebody.
Biology
Aristotle’s really great contribution to natural science was in
biology. Living creatures and their parts provide far richer evidence of form,
and of “final cause” in the sense of design for a particular
purpose, than do inanimate objects. He wrote in detail about five hundred
different animals in his works, including a hundred and twenty kinds of fish
and sixty kinds of insect. He was the first to use dissection extensively. In
one famous example, he gave a precise description of a kind of dog-fish that
was not seen again by scientists until the nineteenth century, and in fact his
work on this point was disbelieved for centuries.
Thus both Aristotle and Plato saw in the living creatures around them
overwhelming evidence for “final causes”, that is to say, evidence
for design in nature, a different design for each species to fit it for its
place in the grand scheme of things. Empedocles, on the other hand, suggested
that maybe creatures of different types could come together and produce mixed
offspring, and those well adapted to their surroundings would survive. This
would seem like an early hint of Darwinism, but it was not accepted, because as
Aristotle pointed out, men begat men and oxen begat oxen, and there was no
evidence of the mixed creatures Empedocles suggested.
Although this idea of the “nature” of things accords well with
growth of animals and plants, it leads us astray when applied to the motion of
inanimate objects, as we shall see.
Elements
Aristotle’s theory of the basic constituents of matter looks to a
modern scientist perhaps something of a backward step from the work of the
atomists and Plato. Aristotle assumed all substances to be compounds of four elements:
earth, water, air and fire, and each of these to be a combination of two of
four opposites, hot and cold, and wet and dry. (Actually, the words he
used for wet and dry also have the connotation of softness and hardness).
Aristotle’s whole approach is more in touch with the way things
present themselves to the senses, the way things really seem to be, as opposed
to abstract geometric considerations. Hot and cold, wet and dry are qualities
immediately apparent to anyone, this seems a very natural way to describe
phenomena. He probably thought that the Platonic approach in terms of abstract
concepts, which do not seem to relate to our physical senses but to our reason,
was a completely wrongheaded way to go about the problem. It has turned out,
centuries later, that the atomic and mathematical approach was on the right
track after all, but at the time, and in fact until relatively recently,
Aristotle seemed a lot closer to reality. He discussed the properties of real
substances in terms of their “elemental” composition at great
length, how they reacted to fire or water, how, for example, water evaporates
on heating because it goes from cold and wet to hot and wet, becoming air, in
his view. Innumerable analyses along these lines of commonly observed phenomena
must have made this seem a coherent approach to understanding the natural
world.
Dynamics: Motion, And Why Things Move
It is first essential to realize that the world Aristotle saw around him in
everyday life was very different indeed from that we see today. Every modern
child has since birth seen cars and planes moving around, and soon finds out
that these things are not alive, like people and animals. In contrast, most of
the motion seen in fourth century Greece was people, animals and birds,
all very much alive. This motion all had a purpose, the animal was moving to
someplace it would rather be, for some reason, so the motion was directed by
the animal’s will. For Aristotle, this motion was therefore
fulfilling the “nature” of the animal, just as its natural growth
fulfilled the nature of the animal.
To account for motion of things obviously not alive, such as a stone
dropped from the hand, he extended the concept of the “nature” of
something to inanimate matter. He suggested that the motion of such inanimate
objects could be understood by postulating that elements tend to seek their
natural place in the order of things, so earth moves downwards most
strongly, water flows downwards too, but not so strongly, since a stone will
fall through water. In contrast, air moves up (bubbles in water) and fire goes
upwards most strongly of all, since it shoots upward through air. This general
theory of how elements move has to be elaborated, of course, when applied to
real materials, which are mixtures of elements. He would conclude that wood,
say, has both earth and air in it, since it does not sink in water.
Natural Motion and Violent Motion
Of course, things also sometimes move because they are pushed. A
stone’s natural tendency, if left alone and unsupported, is to fall, but
we can lift it, or even throw it through the air. Aristotle termed such forced
motion “violent” motion as opposed to natural motion. The term
“violent” here connotes that some external force is applied to the
body to cause the motion. (Of course, from the modern point of view, gravity is
an external force that causes a stone to fall, but even Galileo did not realize
that. Before Newton, the falling of a stone was considered natural motion that
did not require any outside help.)
(Question: I am walking steadily upstairs carrying a large stone when
I stumble and both I and the stone go clattering down the stairs. Is the motion
of the stone before the stumble natural or violent? What about the motion of
the stone (and myself) after the stumble?)
Aristotle’s Laws of Motion
Aristotle was the first to think quantitatively about the speeds
involved in these movements. He made two quantitative assertions about how
things fall (natural motion):
1. Heavier things fall faster, the speed being proportional
to the weight.
2. The speed of fall of a given object depends inversely
on the density of the medium it is falling through, so, for example, the
same body will fall twice as fast through a medium of half the density.
Notice that these rules have a certain elegance, an appealing quantitative
simplicity. And, if you drop a stone and a piece of paper, it’s clear
that the heavier thing does fall faster, and a stone falling through water is
definitely slowed down by the water, so the rules at first appear plausible.
The surprising thing is, in view of Aristotle’s painstaking observations
of so many things, he didn’t check out these rules in any serious way. It
would not have taken long to find out if half a brick fell at half the speed of
a whole brick, for example. Obviously, this was not something he considered
important.
From the second assertion above, he concluded that a vacuum cannot exist,
because if it did, since it has zero density, all bodies would fall through it
at infinite speed which is clearly nonsense.
For violent motion, Aristotle stated that the speed of the
moving object was in direct proportion to the applied force.
This means first that if you stop pushing, the object stops moving. This
certainly sounds like a reasonable rule for, say, pushing a box of books across
a carpet, or a Grecian ox dragging a plough through a field. (This intuitively
appealing picture, however, fails to take account of the large frictional force
between the box and the carpet. If you put the box on a sled and pushed it
across ice, it wouldn’t stop when you stop pushing. Galileo realized the
importance of friction in these situations.)
Planetary Dynamics
The idea that motion (of inanimate objects) can be accounted for in terms of
them seeking their natural place clearly cannot be applied to the planets,
whose motion is apparently composed of circles. Aristotle therefore postulated
that the heavenly bodies were not made up of the four elements earth, water,
air and fire, but of a fifth, different, element called aither, whose
natural motion was circular. This was not very satisfying for various reasons.
Somewhere between here and the moon a change must take place, but where? Recall
that Aristotle did not believe that there was a void anywhere. If the sun has
no heat component, why does sunlight seem so warm? He thought it somehow
generated heat by friction from the sun’s motion, but this wasn’t
very convincing, either.
Aristotle’s Achievements
To summarize: Aristotle’s philosophy laid out an approach to the
investigation of all natural phenomena, to determine form by detailed,
systematic work, and thus arrive at final causes. His logical method of
argument gave a framework for putting knowledge together, and deducing new
results. He created what amounted to a fully-fledged professional scientific
enterprise, on a scale comparable to a modern university science department. It
must be admitted that some of his work - unfortunately, some of the physics -
was not up to his usual high standards. He evidently found falling stones a lot
less interesting than living creatures. Yet the sheer scale of his enterprise,
unmatched in antiquity and for centuries to come, gave an authority to all his
writings.
It is perhaps worth reiterating the difference between Plato and Aristotle,
who agreed with each other that the world is the product of rational design,
that the philosopher investigates the form and the universal, and that the only
true knowledge is that which is irrefutable. The essential difference between
them was that Plato felt mathematical reasoning could arrive at the
truth with little outside help, but Aristotle believed detailed empirical investigations
of nature were essential if progress was to be made in understanding the
natural world.
Books I used to prepare this lecture:
Early Greek Science: Thales to Aristotle, G. E. R. Lloyd, Norton,
N.Y., 1970. An excellent inexpensive paperback giving a more detailed
presentation of many of the subjects we have discussed. My sections on Method
and Causes, in particular, follow Lloyd’s treatment.
History of Western Philosophy, Bertrand Russell. An opinionated but
very entertaining book, mainly on philosophy but with a fair amount of science
and social analysis.
previous
index
next